Objects
have no value without a valuer. It is a valuer's desire for an object
that allows us to impute that object with a value.
We
have the economists of the Austrian School of Economics to primarily
thank for this “subjective theory of value.” Their insight
explains how the market enriches those who trade. Each time a trade
occurs in the market, each party to the transaction values what he
receives more than what he gives.
Subjective
valuation serves as a basis of modern economics because it is so
right as a first approximation of what is happening, but to go
further with the brilliance of the Austrian School's economics, we
need to reexamine some objective contributions to economic value.
Value
is relational – as important as its subjective character is, it is
ultimately about a relationship that exists between the valuer (the
subject) and the valued (the object). Sometimes it has the very
subjective nature of a simple desire of the valuer, but sometimes it
also reveals the specific relationship between the valuer and the
object.
For
example, the Austrians explain interest as the difference between
having a good in the present and having that same good sometime in
the future. They call this difference “time preference.” The
amount of time preference is a result of the subject's mind, but the
fact that it exists and must exist is a result of the object's
location in time.
Like
time preference, it can be said that there is also a space
preference. A subject naturally prefers a pizza from a certain chain
restaurant near his home in Denver to the same pizza from the same
chain restaurant in New York. Because of the objective condition of
space, the one in New York is virtually valueless to him.
Murray
Rothbard would say that the pizzas are actually different and their
different values can be attributed solely to their being different
objects. He argued that ice in winter is a different object than it
is in summer, explaining why it is valueless in winter and
refreshingly valuable in summer. If it has a different value it must
be a different object. But, preserved in a freezer, it is, in fact,
exactly the same object. In this case, Rothard, genius though he was,
was stretching subjectivity in vain to explain all value differences.
The ice's value has changed because it is the relationship between
the subject and object, between a man and the ice positioned in time,
that has changed and it is the relationship itself that creates the
value.
Time
preference is a preference for the SAME object located at a more
proximate point in time. The object is not a different object because
the subject has to wait for it.
Economic
value comes from a relationship – a relationship that could not
exist without the subjective intent of the valuer but must also
involve the object's existence in time and space.